Adele E. Goldberg

Adele E. Goldberg (PDF)

2022 • 29 Pages • 1.78 MB • English
Posted July 01, 2022 • Submitted by Superman

Visit PDF download

Download PDF To download page

Summary of Adele E. Goldberg

Explain Me This Creativity, Competition, and the Partial Productivity of Constructions Adele E. Goldberg Princeton University Press Princeton and Oxford Copyright © 2019 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TR press.princeton.edu All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Control Number: (to come) ISBN 978-0-691-17425-9 ISBN (pbk.) 978-0691-17426-6 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available Editorial: Meagan Levinson and Samantha Nader Production Editorial: Jenny Wolkowicki Jacket/Cover Credit: {~?~to come} Production: Erin Suydam Publicity: Copyeditor: Maia Vaswani This book has been composed in Adobe Text Pro and Gotham Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Chapter 1 Introduction It is easy to take our knowledge of language for granted. We learn language before we carry our first backpack to school, and we use it almost every waking hour of every day. Although we may not have studied quantum theory, or read Homer or James Joyce, we are each expert at using our own native language. The challenge that all learners face becomes more apparent when we try to learn a second language in school or as adults. There are many utterances that are perfectly understandable, but which nonetheless tend to be avoided by native speakers of English. If asked, speakers will agree that there is something mildly “off” about them, even though they may have difficulty articulating exactly why they don’t sound quite right. For example, we might confess that someone is driving us crazy (or bananas or in- sane), but we know that it would sound odd to complain that someone is driving us angry. We know that tall bushes are high bushes, but a high teenager is not necessarily tall. We can be creative in how language is used, but our creativity is constrained in ways that can be hard to articulate. For example, someone can tell me something or tell something to me, but they can only explain this to me; that is, it sounds somewhat unconventional to native speakers of English to say, explain me this. That is what this book aims to explain: when, why, and how native speakers are sometimes creative with language and yet at other times much more conservative. Speakers avoid saying certain things, of course, simply because they want to avoid overtly negative reactions. The following are examples of such ill-advised utterances: Sorry Mom, I didn’t mean to get caught. I only care about my grade in this course. Your nose is too big for your face. But children are not systematically corrected for the types of utterances this volume aims to address, which will hereafter be indicated by a preceding “?” (?explain me this, ?drive him angry, etc.). Caregivers are much more focused on the content of children’s speech than on its form, as long as the message is clear enough. For example, a child who says Me loves you, mommy is more likely to 2 chapter 1 get a hug than a grammar lesson, and a young child who utters an impressively grammatical utterance such as I have just completed a mural on the living-room wall with indelible markers is unlikely to get positive feedback from most parents. The sorts of formulations that native speakers recognize as odd are also not the sorts of formulations that grammar teachers warn against, since they are so rarely uttered by native speakers that no admonishment is needed. To be clear, it is not that one never hears expressions such as ?explain me this (or ?drive him angry), or that all speakers judge them to be equally odd. In fact, speakers’ judgments are gradient and dependent on a number of interrelated factors that are the focus of this book. But corpus and experimental studies con- firm that certain types of utterances are avoided by native speakers much more than would be expected by chance. In order to think about how these aspects of language are learned, it’s worth thinking about what speakers and language learners are trying to do. 1.1 The Puzzle The learner’s goal is to comprehend messages, given the forms she witnesses, and to produce forms, given the messages she wants to convey. Therefore, speakers must learn the ways in which forms and functions are paired in the language(s) they speak. These learned pairings of forms and functions are referred to here as grammatical constructions. Speakers also aim to express their intended messages efficiently and effectively while respecting the conventions of their speech communities, as discussed more below. Constructions generally allow us to apply our linguistic knowledge to new situations and experiences. English tends to be particularly flexible in the ways in which constructions are productive. A few examples of productive uses of familiar constructions are provided in table 1.1, with labels for each grammatical construction provided on the right. TABLE 1.1. Novel linguistic exemplars that demonstrate the productivity of various constructions “Hey man, bust me some fries.” Double-object construction “Can we vulture your table?” Transitive causative construction “Vernon tweeted to say she doesn’t like us.” To infinitive construction “What a bodacious thing to say.” Attributive modification construction Attested examples are cited in quotation marks. Here and below unless otherwise noted, attested examples come from Google. introduction 3 At the same time, the constructions exemplified in table 1.1 resist being used productively with certain verbs or adjectives, even when the intended mean- ing is perfectly clear. Examples that illustrate the lack of full productivity are provided in table 1.2. Under each ill-formed example is a closely related fully acceptable example, in parentheses. The latter are provided to indicate that there are no simple, system-wide explanations for why the odd sentences strike native speakers of English as odd. Thus, constructions can be extended for use with some words (table 1.1), but they are rarely completely productive (table 1.2), even when no general constraints are violated. How is it that native speakers know to avoid certain expressions while nonetheless using language in creative ways? It is no exaggeration to say that this basic question has bedeviled linguists and psychologists for the past four decades. 1.2 The Roadmap The paradox of partial productivity of constructions is what this book aims to address. We will also address several issues that have not widely been viewed as directly related. In particular, chapter 2 includes a discussion of how we learn to circumscribe the meanings of words. Close attention to word meanings reveals that speakers possess a vast amount of rich contextual knowl- edge about what each word means, and about which other words it tends to co-occur with. But, initially, young children make certain errors. They may call the moon a ball, or the mailman Daddy, before they learn and become fluent with other words (specifically, moon and mailman). That is, children need to learn to restrict their use of individual words by witnessing how those words and other words are used in particular contexts. The rest of the book argues that the same mechanisms involved in learning and restricting word meanings are used when learning and restricting grammatical constructions, and that TABLE 1.2. Novel formulations that are judged odd by native speakers ?She explained him the story. (cf. She told/guaranteed him the story.) Double-object construction ?He vanished the rabbit. (cf. He hid/banished the rabbit.) Transitive causative construction ?She considered to say something. (cf. She hoped/planned to say something.) To infinitive construction ?The asleep boy (cf. The astute/sleepy boy) Attributive modification construction 4 chapter 1 this process explains how we come to avoid formulations such as ?explain me this. By beginning with word meanings, I hope to make the discussion of our primary target—the partial productivity of grammatical constructions—more accessible. That is, once we have a better understanding of word meanings, we can tackle grammatical constructions by essentially asking: What would words do? Chapter 3 outlines the various factors that are relevant to our knowledge of how grammatical constructions are used within a given speech community. These include formal properties (syntax), words and partially filled words (mor- phology), meaning (semantics), discourse function (information structure), and social context. An appreciation of these factors is a prerequisite for solving the explain-me-this puzzle. This chapter also highlights the remarkable degree of cross-linguistic variation that exists in how simple clauses are expressed in the world’s languages, in an effort to emphasize just how much people must learn in order to use the constructions in their language appropriately. The proposed solution to the partial productivity puzzle allows both gen- eralizations (table 1.1) and exceptions (table 1.2) to be learned via the same mechanisms. In particular, in chapters 4 and 5, two key factors—coverage and competition—are discussed. Chapter 4 explains how constraints on meaning and use emerge, as witnessed exemplars cluster within the high- dimensional conceptual space in which our representations for language exist. This chapter outlines how clustering licenses creative uses of constructions. In particular, a single factor, coverage, combines variability, type frequency, and similarity; specifically, a new instance is licensed to the extent that the ad hoc category required to contain it has been well attested (has been sufficiently “covered”). Also outlined in this chapter is a useful model for formalizing the required mechanism; namely, an incremental Bayesian clustering algorithm (Barak et al., 2014, 2016; see also Alishahi and Stevenson, 2008; Matusevych et al., 2017). In chapter 5, the critical role of competition is detailed. As we comprehend utterances, we attempt to anticipate what the speaker will say next, and we are able to use what the speaker actually says to improve future predictions through a process of error-driven learning. Repeatedly witnessing certain formulations in certain types of contexts strengthens the connections between those grammat- ical constructions and the intended messages-in-context expressed; this results in conventional formulations becoming more accessible for expressing the types of messages that have been previously witnessed. When there exists a readily available formulation that expresses the intended message in the given context, it usually wins out over potential novel formulations. A special effort is required to buck conventional formulations, although this is possible, for the sake of memorability or playfulness (as in the title of this book). But when there is no introduction 5 readily accessible combination of constructions available to express a speaker’s intended message-in-context, she needs to extend language creatively. The proposal is situated in a larger context in chapter 6. Many studies have demonstrated that children are initially less creative than adults: children behave “conservatively” in that they generalize constructions less freely than adults do. Yet other studies have found that children generalize more broadly than adults. This apparent paradox is reconciled by recognizing that children are less adept at aligning bits of knowledge within their high-dimensional conceptual space: sometimes they fail to recognize relevant parallels across exemplars, at least with sufficient confidence (and so they behave conservatively); other times they fail to recognize or retain relevant distinctions (and so they generalize or sim- plify). Appropriate use of grammatical constructions emerges once the relevant conditioning factors for each construction are learned, and the language user becomes more fluent at accessing the appropriate constructions from memory. Chapter 6 also outlines why adult learners of a second language tend to have particular difficulty avoiding the types of odd formulations this book ad- dresses (including ?explain me this). The suggested reasons go beyond the fact that adults receive less input overall, and that the input they do receive is less well suited to learning. In particular, adult learners need to inhibit their well- practiced native language in order to process a new language, and this appears to lead to a reduced ability to take full advantage of the competition among constructions within the new language. Since competition is argued to be key to constraining generalizations via statistical preemption (chapter 5), second- language learners tend to be more vulnerable to producing certain types of formulations that make sense but which native speakers systematically avoid. Additionally, while adults are generally quicker to discern which dimensions of similarity and dissimilarity are relevant to clustering linguistic representations within their hyper-dimensional conceptual space, they are at the same time prone to miss very subtle similarities and distinctions that are not relevant in their first language. 1.3 The CENCE ME Principles The basic understanding of language that this book outlines is based on the key ideas listed in table 1.3, which are discussed in detail in the following chapters. An acronym of the key words in these principles is eemcnce, but eemcnce would be impossible to pronounce. So, let us instead use an anagram of eemcnce: cence me. “Cence me,” pronounced “sense me,” is intended to emphasize the importance of sensible communication. Cence me also usefully illustrates productivity, since the phrase itself is a novel use of the transitive construction. The cence me principles spell out some key assumptions of the more general 6 chapter 1 usage-based constructionist approach to language that are widely shared (see, e.g., Bybee, 2010; Christiansen and Chater, 2016; Goldberg, 2006; Kapatsinski, 2018; Langacker, 1988; Tomasello, 2003; Traugott and Trousdale, 2013). The approach also shares much with memory-based exemplar-based models (Aha et al., 1991; Bod, 2009; Bybee, 2002; Daelemans and van den Bosch, 2005; Gahl and Yu, 2006; Kruschke, 1992; Nosofsky, 1986). The cence me approach emphasizes that exemplars—structured representations—cluster within a hyper-dimensional conceptual space giving rise to emergent construc- tions, which are then extendable as needed for the purpose of communication. Individual languages can and do vary in striking ways, as will be emphasized, but the usage-based constructionist approach adopted here suggests that the cence me principles are at work in every natural language, serving to constrain and shape the range of possible human languages. The present book emphasizes examples in English because the majority of the experimental and modeling work to be described has been done on English, and because English is the language I know best. My understanding of what a construction is has evolved. Early on, I adopted the following definition: C is a construction if and only if C is a form-meaning pair <Fi, Si> such that some aspect of Fi or some aspect of Si is not strictly predictable from TABLE 1.3. The cence me principles A. Speakers balance the need to be Expressive and Efficient while conforming to the conventions of their speech communities. B. Our Memory is vast but imperfect: memory traces are retained but partially abstract (“lossy”).a C. Lossy memories are aligned when they share relevant aspects of form and function, resulting in overlapping, emergent clusters of representations: Constructions. D. New information is related to old information, resulting in a rich network of constructions. E. During production, multiple constructions are activated and Compete with one another to express our intended message. F. During comprehension, mismatches between what is expected and what is witnessed fine-tune our network of learned constructions via Error-driven learning. a Our representations are “lossy,” a term from computer science, in the sense that they are not fully specified in all detail. introduction 7 C’s component parts or from other previously established constructions. (Goldberg, 1995, 4) Later, I recognized that this definition was too narrow. Our knowledge of language comprises a network of constructions, and we clearly know and re- member conventional expressions even if they are in no way idiosyncratic. So I broadened my definition of constructions as follows: Any linguistic pattern is recognized as a construction as long as some aspect of its form or function is not strictly predictable from its component parts or from other constructions recognized to exist. In addition, patterns are stored as constructions even if they are fully predictable as long as they occur with sufficient frequency. (Goldberg, 2006, 5). The present volume offers a still more inclusive understanding of what con- structions are, motivated by a better appreciation of human memory, learning, and categorization. Here, as explained in the following chapters, constructions are understood to be emergent clusters of lossy memory traces that are aligned within our high- (hyper!) dimensional conceptual space on the basis of shared form, function, and contextual dimensions. Proponents of alternative perspectives or readers who wish to compare the present proposal with other proposals in more detail may find chapter 7 partic- ularly relevant. There, several recent alternative proposals that aim to account for the partial productivity of constructions are discussed. These include, for example, the idea that speakers avoid straying from what they have witnessed (“conservatism via entrenchment”), that it is useful to posit invisible syntactic diacritics or underlying structures without specifying how these are to be iden- tified by learners, that putting a cap on the number of exceptions and a floor on the number of instances that follow a generalization will ensure how and when generalizations are productive (the Tolerance and Sufficiency principles of Yang [2016]), or that incorporating degrees of uncertainty into formal rules is predictive (O’Donnell, 2015). While aspects of each of these proposals have merit, we will see that the usage-based constructionist approach, described by the cence me principles, explains the facts more fully. The final chapter stands back and puts the discussion in a broader context, while raising several outstanding issues that remain to be addressed. 1.4 Speakers Are Efficient and Expressive and also Conform Before leaving this introductory chapter, let’s go over the first of the cence me principles: We aim to express our messages effectively and efficiently while 8 chapter 1 obeying the conventions of our speech communities. To clarify the key terms involved: 1. Expressiveness: Linguistic options must be sufficient for conveying speaker’s thoughts, beliefs, and attitudes in ways that listeners are able to understand. 2. Efficiency: Fewer and shorter constructions are easier to learn and produce than more or longer constructions. 3. Obeying conventions: Learners attempt to use language in the ways that others in their language communities do. A language is only sufficiently expressive if it has the means to adequately con- vey a speaker’s thoughts, beliefs, and attitudes in ways that avoid failures of communication. A maximally expressive language might have an ever-increasing number of words and constructions, with every potential distinction indicated by a unique form. On the other hand, a maximally efficient language would have a single, easy to learn and use form (perhaps the form, ah). The fact that language users need to be both effective and efficient requires natural languages to find a balance between these two opposing factors, as has been long discussed by functional linguists (Briscoe, 1998; Bybee, 1985, 2003; Givón, 1979; Goldberg, 1995; Grice, 1975; Haiman, 1985; Levinson, 1983; Paul, 1888; Slobin, 1977; von Humboldt, [1832] 1999). The recognition that languages must be efficient and expressive, and that these pressures are mutually constraining, has gained new traction within the “noisy-channel” approach to language processing, which recognizes that speak- ers are attempting to express information as efficiently as possible, under imper- fect or noisy conditions (Gibson et al., 2013; Jaeger and Levy, 2006). The noisy- channel approach has emphasized the dynamic nature of the balance between efficient and expressive communication. When a speaker is reasonably certain that an intended message will be successfully conveyed, the balance is tipped toward efficiency, with forms being reduced and distinctions being underspe- cified (Hopper and Traugott, 2003; Jaeger, 2010; Levy, 2008; Levy et al., 2009; Piantadosi et al., 2011, 2012). For example, when a verb appears with the con- struction it most commonly appears in, the verb form itself tends to be reduced (Gahl and Garnsey, 2004). Similarly, the complementizer that is more likely to be omitted when it is predictable in context (Wasow et al., 2011). On the other hand, under noisy or uncertain conditions, distinctions may be exaggerated, and language may be made less ambiguous in various ways (Bradlow and Bent, 2002; Buz et al., 2014; Gibson et al., 2013; Hall et al., 2013). Thus, efficiency and expressiveness balance each other and lead languages to vacillate between using shorter or fewer forms to express a given message on the one hand, and introduction 9 adopting new, longer, or additional forms in order to ensure that messages are understood as intended, on the other. The last idea, that speakers tend to obey the conventions of their language community, captures the fact that humans treat language as a normative enter- prise. For example, people within a given community tend to believe that there is a “right” way to pronounce words, even if other communities are recognized to pronounce them differently. The Gershwins’ famous lyric, “You like tomato and I like tomahto, . . . Let’s call the whole thing off” epitomizes this idea. Humans are a rarity within the animal kingdom in using arbitrary communicative sym- bols that are shared within a community and distinct from those used in other communities (Tomasello, 2016). In fact, humans quite generally appreciate that there are culture-specific “right” and “wrong” ways to do a great many things, and we learn to obey these conventions in a way that other species do not (Boyd and Richerson, 1988; Horner and Whiten, 2005). Many normative conventions are, at least initially, self-conscious; for example, our knowledge about how to eat food politely, whether or how much to tip at restaurants, or whether it is polite to sneeze or burp in public. Other social norms may be obeyed with- out self-conscious awareness, including how close to stand to each other while speaking, or what sort of foods are appropriate for breakfast. The importance of cultural norms for human behavior has enjoyed a long and rich appreciation within philosophy (e.g., Korsgaard and O’Neill, 1996). Our respect for normative patterns of behavior is what allows us to create com- plex cultural practices. For example, dollar bills would be meaningless were it not for the social agreement that imbues them with value. Driving would be terrifying if we couldn’t rely on other drivers to (generally) obey standard driving practices. Again, work that has compared humans with other primates has emphasized that cultural norms may be uniquely human (Tomasello, 2009, 2016), particularly when they serve no clear purpose (e.g., Horner and Whiten, 2005; McGuigan et al., 2011). Normativity is critical to the explain-me-this problem in that generations of learners obey restrictions that do not serve any clear communicative function: we respect the patterns that are evident in the input. For example, even though saying she made it vanish is somewhat less efficient than she vanished it, and even though the latter formulation is readily interpretable, native English speakers avoid the shortcut and normatively obey a shared preference for the periphrastic form. A mechanistic explanation supports our tendency to produce forms that our community deems acceptable, insofar as partially familiar formulations are easier to access than wholly novel formulations. That is, more conventional forms are more efficient to access from memory even if they are less efficient to produce (see section 4.5). But the reason native speakers judge the longer phrase (explain this to me) to be the “right” way to express the intended meaning 10 chapter 1 and the shorter phrase (?explain me this) to be “incorrect,” and the reason that familiarity tends to be more important than ease of articulation, is because we desire to speak like others in our community—language is a social and norma- tive enterprise. Chapter 2 briefly reviews the nature of word meanings and asks how we learn to use words appropriately. We will then see in the following chapters that many of the lessons learned from an appreciation of word meaning extend naturally to our primary question: How do we learn to use basic clause types—argument structure constructions (ASCs)—in creative but constrained ways? Chapter 2 Word Meanings As described in chapter 1, the primary goal of this book is to provide an explana- tion of how native speakers of a language know that they can combine words in certain new ways but not others. I refer to this as the explain-me-this puzzle, since this phrase provides a good example of the phenomenon: the intended meaning of ?explain me this is perfectly clear, but it nevertheless does not sound natural to native speakers of English (hence it is preceded by “?”). Before addressing this issue, we first focus on the simpler case of how speakers learn to use individual words appropriately, because there are several key parallels between the two problems, insofar as both cases require learning how to use language in ways that are creative and yet constrained. 2.1 Meanings Are Rich, Structured, and Partially Abstracted Many of us don’t reflect on word meanings very often, and so we may fail to appreciate just how much intricate knowledge is required for us to use words appropriately. Quite specific knowledge is needed, for example, to distinguish the more than a dozen verbs that imply that a person is forced to leave a situ- ation or place (see table 2.1). Each of these words is appropriate in a distinct range of contexts, even though they all designate the same abstract type of event represented in figure 2.1. Several of the words in table 2.1 imply that the removed person has somehow transgressed; they differ in terms of which organization or place the person is removed from. To banish is to remove a person from civilized society; to expel (in one sense of the word) is to remove from a school; to deport is to remove TABLE 2.1. Partial list of verbs that designate the removal of a person from a situation or place Banish Dismiss Extradite Blackball Evacuate Fire Blacklist Exile Kick out Cast out Expatriate Lay off Deport Expel Oust 12 chapter 2 from a country; to fire is to remove a person from his job. Lay off differs from fire in that there’s no stigma attached to the person who has to leave his job. A person who is blacklisted is barred from some type of work, often unfairly and for political reasons. People can be ousted only if they are political figures. This sort of contextual information or world knowledge is part of our knowledge of language, an observation that will be relevant as we approach the explain-me- this puzzle in the following chapters. Different types of world knowledge are needed for different types of word meanings. Knowledge of quite specific motor se- quences is required to distinguish the meanings of walk, skip, hop, jog, power walk, run, race, sprint, and waltz. While it would be difficult to try to explicitly define these terms, we can identify the actions at a glance. Moreover, we have contingent associations with many of these terms because of how they have been witnessed in the past. We know that skipping is most often done by chil- dren and is associated with being carefree, power walking is more commonly done in malls and by mothers or retirees, and waltzing is associated with formal events such as weddings. In fact, once you start to think of the actual range of words that we know, it becomes clear that word meanings are not readily reducible to any finite list of recognizable features or attributes (Fodor et al., 1980) and word meanings are not easily disentangled from knowledge about real-world contexts in which these words tend to occur (Palmer, 1996; Willits et al., 2015). For example, if asked to try to define the word bachelor, many people will suggest “unmarried man” (Fillmore, 1975), a meaning that is often cited in philosophy classes be- cause it seems to be definable in terms of simple features: unmarried and male. But this definition would seem to classify as bachelors the Pope, Tarzan, unmar- ried men with long-term live-in partners, and unmarried men on life-support. As Fillmore noted long ago, something clearly seems to be missing from this definition. He pointed out that the meaning of bachelor actually seems to be de- fined against a background of stereotypical world knowledge. This stereotypical knowledge takes for granted that boys grow up, date multiple people for a period of time, get married and stay married. Within this stereotype, there is clearly a period of time when an unmarried man is a bachelor. Fillmore suggested that each word meaning evokes a conventional semantic frame, where a frame is a structured abstraction or idealization over a set of coherent contexts (Fillmore, 1975, 1977, 1982, 1984; see also closely related ideas by Austin, 1962; Bartlett, 1932; Lakoff, 1987; Langacker, 1987). The word bachelor profiles an unmarried man, but it includes the relevant background frame of the stereotypical series FIGURE 2.1. Concrete de- piction of the general type of abstract event profiled by the verbs in table 2.1. word meanings 13 of events just mentioned. When the background frame does not apply, neither does the word. Semantic frames capture rich aspects of our world knowledge as is required for adequate characterizations of word meanings. Experimental work has found support for the psychological relevance of contextually evoked semantic frames of knowledge. For example, Bar (2004) has demonstrated that people perceive the same visually filtered shape to unambiguously be a hairdryer, if placed in the context of a bathroom sink, but to be a drill if placed in the context of a workbench (see also Beck and Kastner, 2009; Biederman et al., 1982; Murphy and Wisniewski, 1989; Walther et al., 2009; Zettersten et al., 2018). When we interpret individual words, neural areas that relate those words to various actions or perceptions may also be reliably activated, suggesting that our sensory knowl- edge, whether directly experienced or imagined, is linked to word meanings. More specifically, words referring to actions performed by the leg, arm, or face (e.g., kick, pick, or lick) have been found to evoke activation at or near the areas in the primary motor cortex that are active when we move our feet, hands, or tongue (Hauk et al., 2004). Activation of our motor cortex is also evoked when certain words are used metaphorically—e.g., to grasp the idea, to kick an idea around (Cacciari et al. 2011; Desai et al. 2011; Pulvermüller et al., 2005). Texture- selective regions in the somatosensory cortex are likewise activated by words related to texture, whether used literally or metaphorically—e.g., She had a rough day (Lacey et al., 2012)—and cortical areas that are evoked by tasting food are activated when words related to taste are used in isolation or in conventional metaphors—e.g., That was a bitter breakup (Citron and Goldberg, 2014). In fact, different words reliably evoke activation that spans almost the entire cortex, suggesting that word meaning can involve a wide range of associations (Bergen, 2012; Huth et al., 2016). Thus, words evoke rich conceptual and perceptual in- formation gleaned from the contexts in which the words have been witnessed. 2.2 Vast Implicit Memory How do we learn the rich structured representations required for word mean- ing? One prominent philosopher found the question so challenging that he concluded that we must actually be born with all possible current, past, and future word meanings, so that our job as learners is merely to attach a label to an already existing concept (Fodor, 1975). But this idea leads to the uncomfortable stipulation that Abraham Lincoln was born with meanings (if not labels) for concepts such as computer, fax, and drone, and that your grandmother was born with knowledge of the meanings of frack, twerk, and rap. This seems unlikely. It is clear that even a single initial encounter with a word can potentially leave a memory trace of its use. Why is this clear? Consider the counterfactual: if no

Related books

e-Journal - e-Book List User Guide

2022 • 2 Pages • 475.95 KB

Archiving e-Journals - STM

2022 • 45 Pages • 1.31 MB

List of e-Journals

2022 • 76 Pages • 1.05 MB

E-PORTFOLIOS @ TEACHER TRAINING - ERIC

2022 • 9 Pages • 691.7 KB

Time Management in E-learning - CiteSeerX

2022 • 5 Pages • 783.91 KB

e-Business 2.0; Roadmap for Success

2022 • 361 Pages • 6.83 MB

THE SUCCESS OF E-COMMERCE STARTUPS

2022 • 24 Pages • 605.7 KB

Tavistock and Portman E-PRINTS Online

2022 • 6 Pages • 104.18 KB

MEASURING E-TEXTBOOK QUALITY; COMBINING KANO

2022 • 7 Pages • 787.79 KB

MEASURING THE USER SATISFACTION OF E

2022 • 1 Pages • 491.1 KB